viernes, 31 de agosto de 2018

Reifing nature - Mike Michael


This returns us to Latour's advocacy of a strategic realism (infrareflexivity).

If what we aim to do is convince others via our polished representations, and

if part of this process entails the attempted inoculation of our texts against

the outrages of the deconstructionists who everywhere lie in wait, one option

is to evoke and invoke the real as energetically and cannily as possible. This

'real' could be the typically 'social' (e.g. interests, values, institutional positioning

and the like), or it could be the typically 'non-social' and 'nonhuman' .

It all depends on the contexts and exigencies - both social and non-social.


Thus to 'reify' the environmental crisis, animal suffering or human disease

and despair is perfectly acceptable when one's purpose is to enable and

encourage political action and to enrol others as political activists.

Mike Michael , 1997 - PP 39

lunes, 27 de agosto de 2018

Oslak - 1994

Oslak 1994 -
"No existe ni ha existido, por lo tanto, una voluntad expansiva del estado con independencia de la
voluntad de quienes lo han conducido, colonizado o explotado en su beneficio. Y sin embargo, los
que hoy propician retóricamente su encogimiento son los propios sectores que casi siempre fueron
sus principales beneficiarios. En su discurso, los motes "estado empresario" y "estado empleador"
simbolizan la hipertrofia y el gigantismo. "Olvidan" agregar que los estados contratista, comprador y
subsidiador, otras de las caras de este Jano multifronte, fueron tanto o más responsables de esa
expansión. Obviamente, sólo a través de ciertas formas de influencia o control ejercidas por dichos
sectores, pudieron desarrollarse estas otras formas de intervención estatal que acabaron
engrosando sus instituciones y recursos. "

" Puede  advertirse  que  estas  críticas  de  izquierda  y  derecha  destacaban,  en  realidad,  dos   fenómenos  diferentes:  por  una  parte,  el  impacto  de  la  organización  estatal  sobre  la  estructura  de   poder de la sociedad moderna; y, por otra, la índole de su función social, es decir, su capacidad y  posibilidades  de  servir  a  objetivos  de  interés  general  (Oszlak,  1976,  1984).  Es  decir,  el  temprano   cuestionamiento del estado tuvo dos fundamentos dife rentes. El más explícito consistió en declarar  -como ocurre actualmente- la incompetencia del estado para la gestión de los asuntos sociales, su  menor  productividad  y  eficiencia  frente  a  otras  instancias  de  gestión.  El  menos  visible,  el   cuestionamiento del poder adquirido por el mismo frente a otros actores sociales.  "

Link : http://unpan1.un.org/intradoc/groups/public/documents/un-dpadm/unpan040064.pdf

miércoles, 1 de agosto de 2018

Bourdieu - Actor Racional



“The ‘rational actor’ theory, which seeks the ‘origin’ of acts,    strictly economic or not, in an ‘intention’ of  ‘consciousness’, is    often associated with a narrow conception of the ‘rationality’ of    practices, an economism which regards as rational (or, which amounts    to the same thing in this logic, as economic) those practices that are    consciously oriented by the pursuit of maximum (economic) profit at    minimum (economic) cost. Finalist economism explains practices by    relating them directly and exclusively to economic interests, treated    as consciously posited ends; mechanistic economism relates them no    less directly and exclusively to economic interests, defined just as    narrowly but treated as causes. Both are unaware that practices can    have other principles than mechanical causes or conscious ends and can    obey an economic logic without obeying narrowly economic interests.    There is an economy of practices, a reason immanent in practices,    whose ‘origin’ lies neither in the ‘decisions’ of reason understood as    rational calculation nor in the determinations of mechanisms external    to and superior to the agents. Being constitutive of the structure of    rational practice, that is, the practice most appropriate to achieve    the objectives inscribed in the logic of a particular field at the    lowest cost, this economy can be defined in relation to all kinds of    functions, one of which, among others, is the maximization of monetary    profit, the only one recognized by economism. In other words, if one    fails to recognize any form of action other than rational action or    mechanical reaction, it is impossible to understand the logic of all    the actions that are reasonable without being the product of a    reasoned design, still less of rational calculation; informed by a    kind of objective finality without being consciously organized in    relation to an explicitly constituted end; intelligible and coherent    without springing from an intention of coherence and a deliberate    decision; adjusted to the future without being the product of a    project or a plan. And, if one fails to see that the economy described    by economic theory is a particular case of a whole universe of    economies, that is, of fields of struggle differing both in the stakes    and scarcities that are generated within them and in the forms of    capital deployed in them, it is impossible to account for the specific    forms, contents and leverage points thus imposed on the pursuit of    maximum specific profits and on the very general optimizing strategies    (of which economic strategies in the narrow sense are one form among    others). (p. 50-51)

Economism is a form of ethnocentrism. Treating pre-capitalist    economies, in Marx’s phrase, ‘as the Fathers of the Church treated the    religions which preceded Christianity’, it applies to them categories,    methods (economic accountancy, for example) or concepts (such as the    notions of interest, investment or capital) which are the historical    product of capitalism and which induce a radical transformation of    their object, similar to the historical transformation from which they    arose. Economism recognizes no other form of interest than that which    capitalism has produced, through a kind of real operation of    abstraction, by setting up a universe of relations between man and man    based, as Marx says, on ‘callous cash payment’ and more generally by    favouring the creation of relatively autonomous fields, capable of    establishing their own axiomatics (through the fundamental tautology    ‘business is business’, on which ‘the economy’ is based). It can    therefore find no place in its analyses, still less in its    calculations, for any form of ‘non-economic’ interest. It is as if    economic calculation had been able to appropriate the territory    objectively assigned to the remorseless logic of what Marx calls    ‘naked self-interest’, only by relinquishing an island of the    ‘sacred’, miraculously spared by the ‘icy waters of egoistic    calculation’, the refuge of what has no price because it has too much    or too little. But, above all, it can make nothing of universes that    have not performed such a dissociation and so have, as it were, an    economy in itself and not for itself. Thus, any partial or total    objectification of the archaic economy that does not include a theory    of the subjective relation of misrecognition which agents adapted to    this economy maintain with its ‘objective’ (that is, objectivist)    truth, succumbs to the most subtle and most irreproachable form of    ethnocentrism. […]    By reducing this economy to its ‘objective’ reality, economism    annihilates the specificity located precisely in the socially    maintained discrepancy between the ‘objective’ reality and the social    representation of production and exchange. It is no accident that the    vocabulary of the archaic economy is entirely made up of double-sided    notions that are condemned to disintegrate in the very history of the    economy, because, owing to their duality, the social relations that    they designate represent unstable structures which inevitably split in    two as soon as the social mechanisms sustaining them are weakened.”    (p. 112-3)"        

Source: https://economicsociology.org/2017/07/19/pierre-bourdieu-economism-is-a-form-of-ethnocentrism/



"Bourdieu evoca um continuum de atividades muito diversas, no qual a atividade de produção simbólica do produto ocupa um lugar mais ou menos importante, tendo cada um sua especificidade. A alta costura, por exemplo, caracteriza-se pela necessidade de inovação permanente. A produção automobilística notabiliza-se entre outras pela preocupação com o design , a criação de marcas e de modelos. Enquanto os autores da economia neoclássica, e mesmo sociólogos que limitam sua atenção à especificidade da economia de certos bens "diferentes de outros", qualificam de "standards " os bens de uso quotidiano, Bourdieu faz referência aos produtos que possuem uma carga simbólica mais ou menos importante: como em A distinção (1979), o sentido atribuído aos produtos ou às práticas não pode ser pensado de modo essencialista, porém relativo. O caráter "standard" ou "simbólico" dos bens não pode ser visto como uma propriedade intrínseca. A distinção entre bens "standard" e bens simbólicos é uma disputa e um instrumento de lutas no espaço em que as trocas econômicas ocorrem. Nada é mais classificador em relação ao indivíduo que seu endereço, a aparência de sua casa, seu modo de se vestir, de comer ou, ainda, a marca de seu carro. Esses são os gostos associados ao quotidiano, que os economistas nomeiam de "preferências reveladas", explicam o sentido da boutade segundo a qual "os classificadores são classificados por sua classificação" (Bourdieu, 1979)." 

Marie-France Garcia-Parpet (2013)
http://www.scielo.br/pdf/sant/v3n5/2238-3875-sant-03-05-0091.pdf
http://www.scielo.br/scielo.php?script=sci_arttext&pid=S2238-38752013000500091

Zukerfeld 2017 - Premio ESOCITE 2018

"Now, at first glance it could seem strange that we consider individual or collective subjects (although actually it is the knowledge that they carry) as an output of some productive processes. Resistance to this idea could have at least two root causes: on the one hand, humanist ontological inertia. On the other hand, a vague idea that productive processes result in ‘goods and services’ and not subjects. In terms of the first, in effect the dominant ontology, especially since industrial capitalism, accustoms us to making a rigid division between objects and subjects: it is a tacit but firmly held belief that objects are produced, but subjects are not. Of course, denaturalising and rejecting this perspective is not at all novel. There are recent and fashionable antecedents in Foucault ([1966] 2002), but above all in Haraway (1991, 1992), Fuller (2009), Sloterdijk (2016) and many more. Unfortunately, these authors do not usually recognise that it is Hegel who, in Phenomenology of Spirit, shows with clarity that subjects produce themselves at the same time as they produce the world. Our concept of productive processes aims to take this Hegelian element and combine it with more contemporary ideas and, above all, to bring it to bear on the historical, empirical, and even economic terrain (although in a different sense to Marx)."

"On the other hand, we are accustomed to associating the result of productive processes with goods and/or certain services. Let us explore this a little. Goods, that is, entities that survive the moment of their production and over which property rights can be exercised, are varied. For example, tables, paper airplanes, software, or texts. Even though the last two are of a particular type (informational goods), it is not difficult to understand that all these examples emerge from something that it is appropriate to call productive processes, which are not necessarily commodity production processes but could be the fruits of leisure time or production for personal consumption."

Zukerfeld 2017 - PP 106 -  "Knowledge Flows: From Translation to Capitalism"

Steve Fuller (2006) - Introduction

"At the moment, STS suffers from a complacency that results from thinking
that because things can always be otherwise, we never need to commit to anything.
This inference works only if one is a disappointed foundationalist, not
someone who takes seriously that the future is largely what we collectively
I make of it. In this respect, STS as normally practiced is much less of a threat to
the future of science than scientists think. Indeed, we shall see in what follows
that the Science Wars have been so far largely a comedy of errors. Nevertheless,
there is something quite serious at stake-and worth arguing about-that
these pages endeavor to reveal."


"Seen from the inside, all sustainable social practices are rational.
Thus, when practices seem irrational to an outsider, such as the sociologist,
that is probably because she is applying a framework alien to the insiders. This
move has significant implications for the historical study of science"

"By the time we reach this point, it is fair to ask whether STS's failure to recognize
the "epistemic" character of science removes it from the sociology of
knowledge. However we answer this question, the phenomenon is itself worthy
of study as an episode in the sociology of knowledge. The techno scientific turn
may be radical from the standpoint of the intellectual history of STS, but it
also provides an explication, perhaps even legitimation, for associated social
tendencies that have accompanied the decline of the welfare state and the rise
of neo-liberalism. These are associated with the claims that we live in "knowledge
societies" ( Stehr 1 994) in need of "knowledge management" ( Fuller
2002a)."

Steve Fuller (2006)

Sociotécnico

  Sociotécnica -> Adjetivo RAE: No existe la palabra sociotécnico en español sino “socio-“ Del lat. socius 'socio', 'comp...